Sunday, November 11, 2007

How to Do Philosophy, vol. 1

As a public service, I would like to list some common kinds of responses to putative counter-examples. Now, the next time you're working on something and a good counter-example comes up, merely consult this list and adapt your favorite response. Feel free to mix and match.

You're welcome.

1) Bite the bullet: "This isn't a counter-example. I don't care what you say, but your example isn't an instance of F. Our intuitions about Fs are systematically wrong." Cover your ears and start humming loudly.
2) Tu Quoque/poison the well: "This counter-example is actually a problem for you, too. You might think your theory gives the right results here, but it doesn't." Feel free to stretch the counter-example and your opponent's theory until it becomes a problem for them.
3) Change your theory: "Your counter-example can be accommodated by a simple generalization of my theory." Feel free to change your theory as much as you'd like, make it ridiculously disjunctive, but remind your reader that it's still the same theory.
4) Vicious ad hominem: "Your response is motivated only by your irrational approach to the topic/other philosophical commitments/bad hygiene/lack of meaningful love life."
5) Reject conceptual analysis: "Sure, this is a counter-example, but I was never giving necessary and sufficient conditions in the first place. Conceptual analysis is dead anyway, right?" Cite Wittgenstein extensively.
6) Distraction/Change of Topic: "Well, sure, but in order to know that your case is a good counter-example, we'd have to know that we're not brains in vats!" or "Yes, this is a good counterexample, but -- look, monkeys!!"
7) Repeat your opponent's theory in a funny voice: (in a high-pitched, squeaky voice) "Look at me, I'm Van Inwagen, and I think that composition only occurs in the case of organisms!" (note: this works best in person)
8) Accept that this is a counterexample and that your life's work is for naught. Drop out, start a rock band. I'll play bass guitar.

Am I missing any?

Monday, October 29, 2007

Many-One Identity Relations

Some people (ahem) want to discuss the notion of a many-one identity relation. I'm a bit puzzled by such talk, since I think it's constitutive of our concept of identity that it's one-one. We don't balk at cases like "Benjamin Franklin is the inventor of bifocals", "Hesperus is Phosphorous", and "Cat Stevens is Yusuf Islam". We might even have many-many cases of identity, like "The candidates who raise the most money are the candidates who get the most votes", though there might be a good way to analyze this in first-order predicate logic with the usual representation of identity. I'm not exactly sure what to make of many-many claims, but set them aside for now.

One has plenty of examples of identity in language from which we try to build our notion, and or familiar identity sign is doing a pretty good job of this. If many-one identity were part of our ordinary concept of identity, we should expect to see all sorts of ordinary uses of it. So, what are the cases that force us to consider a many-one notion? If many-one identity is supposed to be so intuitive, how come we don't see examples of it? How come all uses of it seem ungrammatical and weird?

The only (ordinary) examples I can think of are examples that involve the Trinity. The Father, Son, and Holy Ghost are (is?) one thing, which is God. Is your claim that many-one identity makes exactly as much sense as the Catholic Trinity?

[Note, by the way, that I don't think that claims about intuitions and linguistics are deeply informative about the nature of reality. I'm also not claiming that there's no room for some kind of generalized notion of identity to explain what we mean by "nothing over and above" kinds of claims. I just think it's a mistake to identify this notion with our ordinary uses of identity.]

Saturday, October 20, 2007

Many-One Identity

I believe it makes perfect sense to say that some things xx are identical to one thing y. The table is identical to the four legs and table-top; my two legs, two arms, head, and torso are identical to me; etc. I wonder what your immediate gut reactions are to such claims.

-Einar

PS: I also wonder about your reactions to my last entry. Come on, let's bring this blog back to life!

Saturday, October 13, 2007

Perfectly Natural Irreducibly Plural Properties

Consider the property of being scattered. It has the logical form: S(xx), where 'xx' takes any plurality as value (including a plurality consisting of only one thing, if one thing can be scattered). The property of being scattered has a fixed adicity (one-place), and it is an intrinsic property (or so it seems).

My question is: Can there be any perfectly natural (fundamental) properties of the logical form F(xx)?

-Einar

Sunday, October 7, 2007

In the interests of getting this bog going again, and as an intuition check:

What do you make of the following statement:

(1) If it were to rain and not rain, then it would rain.

Does this strike you as trivially true, non-trivially true, or false?

Monday, August 6, 2007

There are no distributable properties?

Prima facie, there are distributional properties, distributable properties, and they are distinct. It is one thing, Josh Parsons (2004) suggests, to have a redness distribution (say, to be red in such-and-such places but not in others) and another to be just plain red. What I’m interesting in is the claim that there are no distributable properties; there are just distributional properties. Is this a coherent proposal?

One might object as follows. Suppose that D is a distributional property. Intuitively, the instantiation of D involves a distribution of instances of some distributable property D*. On the current proposal, there simply is no property like D*, so the instantiation of D cannot literally involve a distribution of D*-instances. But then how are we to understand what it is for D to be instantiated in the first place? Just as distributors need material to distribute, distributional properties need distributable properties distribute.

I think the thing to say in response to this concern is that it mistakenly, though understandably, assumes that the sense in which distributional properties are ‘distributional’ lines up closely with the everyday sense of the term. Instead, we should think of ‘distributional property’ more as a technical term.

I do not mean to suggest, however, that the notion of distributional property we are working with here is obscure. Suppose that Frank, pointing to Gary who is grimacing and then to Albert who is smiling, says, “There is pain to the left and pleasure to the right.” One might claim in this case that a proper part of the world consisting of Frank, Gary, and Albert involves a distribution of distributable properties including being in pain and having pleasure. Let us call this way of understanding distributional properties the ordinary conception of distributional properties.

One might claim instead that the proper part of the world mentioned above instantiates the distributional property being in pain-to-the-left-and-pleasure-to-the-right. Here the idea is that the truth-maker for Frank’s claim is that the Frank-Gary-Albert fusion instantiates the single aforementioned property. In this case the fusion does not instantiate being in pain and having pleasure qua distributable properties because there are no such properties. To contrast this conception of distributional properties with the ordinary one, call it the minimalist conception (given its commitment to distributional properties but not distributable properties).

Both the ordinary conception and the minimalist conception, as far as I can tell, are coherent, so it seems to me that so far we have not been given a good reason to think that the claim that there are distributional properties but no distributable properties is incoherent. What do you all think?

-Kelly

Thursday, June 21, 2007

An Argument Against Unrestricted Composition

What's wrong with this argument?

www.logicoontologicalissues.blogspot.com

-Einar